What does it mean to say that someone is responsible for something? It turns out that the concept of responsibility is both vague and ambiguous. Let us say that someone is casually responsible for something E in virtue of actively contributing causally to E’s production.Footnote 1 Being causally responsible for something E is not enough, all by itself, for being morally responsible for E, where moral responsibility includes also the possibility of the appropriate application of the retrospective, reactive attitudes of praise or blame.Footnote 2 But being causally responsible does seem to be necessary for being morally responsible.Footnote 3

What else is necessary for being morally responsible? Although there is sharp disagreement about this,Footnote 4 it seems to me that moral responsibility requires the capacity for foresight, the capacity for causal contribution, and the capacity for intentional action directed at a particular outcome. But I will not argue for these claims here, and as far as I can tell, nothing I say in this chapter assumes that they are correct. It is important to note that one could satisfy all of the criteria for being morally responsible for something that is neutral, so that one does not deserve praise or blame for it—rather than create a new category of responsibility to cover this kind of case, we should just keep in mind its possibility.Footnote 5

Consider the following thesis:

  • Divine Moral Responsibility: God is morally responsible to some substantial degree for the occurrence of every contingent event.

There seems to be strong support for Divine Moral Responsibility from the Jewish, Christian, and Islamic traditions (e.g., see Freddoso 1988). In virtue of creating and sustaining the contingent universe, God contributes causally to every contingent event. Furthermore, God has the maximum capacity for foresight possible, and the greatest possible capacity for intentional action directed at particular outcomes.Footnote 6

But suppose that there are ontologically random events in the universe, events which have no sufficient cause and could have turned out differently in some respect, given the same initial conditions and laws of nature. Would the existence of such random events count against Divine Moral Responsibility? To explore this question, I will begin with a much-discussed approach to the problem of evil and God’s responsibility for free creaturely actions before turning to questions about shared moral responsibility.

1 Augustinian Approaches to Evil

How could a perfectly good creator make a less than perfectly good world? Historically, the most popular approach to answering this question involves trying to blame the imperfections of the created world on created agents, rather than the creator, where such created agents are viewed as introducing randomness into the world in a way that provides some casual distance between God and evil. This strategy typically assumes that if one person is fully morally responsible for something, then nobody else is morally responsible to any degree for that same thing. In this section, I will explore the role that this assumption plays in typical Augustinian approaches to the problem of evil, and then explain in the next section why it is false.

Contemporary interest in the problem of evil can be traced to rigorous formulations of the problem generated by J. L. Mackie (1955) and H. J. McCloskey (1960). Their articles led to influential responses from John Hick (1966) and Alvin Plantinga (1974a, b), among others. In his survey of historical approaches to the problem, Hick distinguished between two groups of theodicies, the Augustinian and Irenaean, where the former explains evil as an accidental by-product of the free choices of creatures, and the latter explains it as necessary for moral development (“soul-making”).Footnote 7Hick himself defended an Irenaean approach, whereas Plantinga developed a highly technical formulation of the Augustinian approach called the Free Will Defense. Plantinga’s Augustinian approach has received the lion’s share of attention in the literature, and I will return to it later. But it will be helpful to begin with St. Augustine himself in order to explain in more general terms how assumptions about causality and moral responsibility function in an Augustinian approach.Footnote 8

In trying to explain how “the goods pursued by sinners are in no way evil things, and neither is free will itself,” St. Augustine says that

When the will clings to the common and unchangeable good, it attains the great and foremost goods for human beings. … But when the will turns away from the unchangeable and common good toward its own private good, or toward external or inferior things, it sins. (St. Augustine 1993, 68)

This movement of the will, the turning away from a higher good to embrace a lower one, is the essence of evil, according to Augustine.Footnote 9 Since this movement is “not coerced, but voluntary, it is justly and deservedly punished with misery” (Augustine 1993, 68). What is the cause of this movement of the will, one might ask? Augustine answers:

But perhaps you are going to ask what is the source of this movement by which the will turns away from the unchangeable good toward a changeable good. This movement is certainly evil, even though free will itself is to be counted among good things, since no one can live rightly without it. For if that movement, that turning away from the Lord God, is undoubtedly sin, surely we cannot say that God himself is the cause of sin. So that movement is not from God. (St. Augustine 1993, 69)

St. Augustine seems to argue here as follows:

  1. 1.

    If God were the cause of evil, then God would be morally responsible for evil.

  2. 2.

    God is not morally responsible for evil.

Therefore,

  1. 3.

    God is not the cause of evil.

Although there are questions (to which I shall return later) about what exactly it is saying, to defend premise 2, the Augustinian might offer the following argument:

  1. 4.

    If a created person S performs an evil action A freely, then God does not cause S’s performance of A.

  2. 5.

    If God does not cause created person S’s performance of an evil action A, then God is not morally responsible to any degree for S’s performance of A.

Therefore,

  1. 6.

    If a created person S performs an evil action A freely, then God is not morally responsible to any degree for S’s performance of A.

There is something to be said in defense of each of these premises. First, premise 4 reflects the Augustinian’s libertarian view of the nature of free action, according to which an action is free only if it is not determined. This view of freedom, which implies what I have called ontological randomness, seems essential to the Augustinian approach to the problem of evil.Footnote 10 As Plantinga says, “Now God can create free creatures, but He can’t cause or determine them to do only what is right. For if He does so, then they aren’t significantly free after all; they do not do what is right freely” (Plantinga 1974a, 30). One of Plantinga’s most vocal critics, J. L. Mackie, seems to agree:

[The Free Will Defense] alone allows the theist to admit that there are some real and unabsorbed evils, some items which the world would, from however broad and ultimate a perspective, be better without (so that this is not the best of all possible worlds), and yet at the same time to detach their occurrence from God, to show them as not having been chosen by God.. (Mackie 1982, 156)

Second, premise 5 is a clear consequence of the following general principle:

  1. 7.

    A person S is morally responsible for something E to some degree only if S causes E.

However, the inference from 4 and 5 to 6 is problematic. In order for 4 to be true, the word “cause” must be understood as “provide a causally sufficient condition,” because God clearly provides many causally necessary conditions for creaturely free action (more on this later). To avoid equivocation, then, “cause” must be understood in the same way in 5 (and hence in 7). But in general, providing a causally sufficient condition for an event E is not necessary for being morally responsible for E.Footnote 11 For example, “If two people pick up a heavy rock [together] and chuck it on a third person’s head, both will be responsible for the consequent injury” (Zimmerman 1985b, 355). So 5 and 7 are not plausible if “cause” is understood in the way that is required for 4 to be true. Could the Augustinian argument be revised in order to accommodate this fact about causation and moral responsibility?

Here is the most natural and straightforward way to revise 7 in order to meet this objection:

  1. 8.

    A person S is morally responsible to some degree for something E only if S contributes causally to the production of E to some degree.

From 8, one might infer 9:

  1. 9.

    If God does not contribute causally to any degree to a created person S’s performance of an evil action A, then God is not morally responsible to any degree for S’s performance of A.

These revisions yield the following version of the Augustinian argument:

  1. 10.

    If a created person S performs an evil action A freely, then God does not contribute causally to any degree to S’s performance of evil action A (replacing 4).

  1. 9.

    If God does not contribute causally to any degree to a created person S’s performance of an evil action A, then God is not morally responsible to any degree for S’s performance of A (replacing 5).

Therefore

  1. 6.

    If a created person S performs an evil action A freely, then God is not morally responsible to any degree for S’s performance of A.

Before commenting on the strength of this argument, I should point out that throughout the chapter, I am talking about causation in the sense of efficient causation (not formal, final, or material causation, to use Aristotelian terminology). Even if God does not exist on the same ontological plane as creatures, as some people say, traditional theists hold that God is an efficient cause of the obtaining of various states of affairs in the world, whether or not God’s causation involves other created agents as intermediaries.

Returning now to the argument: it is clearly valid, but according to traditional theism, the first premise (i.e., proposition 10) is false. This is because according to traditional theism, God creates, sustains, and co-operates with the action of every created cause in the world, including free human beings (see the discussion of this point in Freddoso 1988); so God must contribute causally to the performance of every creaturely action, even those evil human actions that are free in a libertarian sense. But since God’s causal contribution is not sufficient, all by itself, for the performance of those evil actions, and God does not intend them per se, the Augustinian approach outlined earlier would insist that God is not to be blamed for them.Footnote 12 As the sixteenth-century Spanish Jesuit theologian Luis de Molina says,

From what has been said we have it only that our morally evil actions are not attributed to God as to a positive cause who has an influence on them. This is in accord with the example of the workman who produces swords. For just as the deeds which are done by those who do not use the swords rightly are not imputed to the workman (for the swords are indifferent with respect to good or bad use), but are instead imputed to the free choice of those who use the swords badly, so too, since God’s general concurrence is indifferent with respect to good and evil actions, the evil actions should not be attributed to God, but should rather be attributed to those who abuse God’s general concurrence in order to do evil. (Molina 1989)

In other words, since created persons freely determine for themselves whether their actions are good or evil, they are completely morally responsible for this, and therefore God is not. St. Augustine seems to agree:

There is nothing I feel so firmly and so intimately as that I have a will by which I am moved to enjoy something. If the will by which I choose or refuse things is not mine, then I don’t know what I can call mine. So if I use my will to do something evil, whom can I hold responsible but myself? (St. Augustine 1993, 72)

Perhaps, then, the following argument captures better than the previous ones the Augustinian approach to the problem of evil:

  1. 11.

    If a created person S performs an evil action A freely, then S is fully morally responsible for performing A.

  2. 12.

    If one person is fully morally responsible for something E, then no other person is morally responsible to any degree for E.

Therefore,

  1. 6.

    If a created person S performs an evil action A freely, then God is not morally responsible to any degree for S’s performance of A.

This argument seems to capture the essence of the Augustinian approach. But is this argument sound, assuming that free creaturely action involves the kind of randomness described earlier? If so, then it seems that Divine Moral Responsibility is false, because God is not morally responsible to any degree for creaturely evil actions. And a parallel argument would seem to show that God is not morally responsible to any degree for any free creaturely actions at all, whether good or evil—but this would seem to be quite problematic, at least from the point of view of traditional theism.

2 Zimmerman on Shared Responsibility

It seems to me that Michael J. Zimmerman has shown that premise 12 is false.Footnote 13 In this section, I will present and extend his arguments for this conclusion. Along the way, I will also criticize his arguments for the view that degree of causal contribution is not a factor in determining degree of moral responsibility.

Zimmerman discusses possible cases of group action which are either oversupplied (i.e., “there is a greater supply of agents involved in the action than is in fact causally necessary for the outcome at issue”) or standard (i.e., not oversupplied: see Zimmerman 1985a, 116). According to Zimmerman, group action involves more than one individual acting together in such a way that each one contributes causally to a single outcome.Footnote 14 Consider the following case of standard group action, to which Zimmerman refers as case X:

Imagine a group of teenagers pushing a large boulder off a plateau, so that it rolls down a slope and wrecks a car at the bottom. Each of the teenagers intends to contribute to the damage to the car and freely participates in the enterprise, in the full knowledge that his contribution to the enterprise is required if the boulder is to be shifted and the car wrecked at all. (Zimmerman 1985a, 116)

Zimmerman argues that in this case, each of the teenagers involved is fully morally responsible for the damage to the car. His argument for this interesting conclusion involves an appeal to a slightly different case, Y, which differs from case X in only one respect: in Y, just one of the teenagers involved in case X is present (let’s call him “S”), and this teenager wrecks the car all by himself. In this case, Zimmerman claims, “there would be no hesitation in ascribing to S full (that is undiminished; not merely sole) responsibility for the damage” (116). In both cases, S’s action is causally necessary but not causally sufficient by itself for the damage (since S’s action requires the co-operation of other factors or agents in both cases, such as the boulder being able to be moved, the boulder and the car being properly positioned relative to one another, the force of gravity, etc.). More formally, here is Zimmerman’s argument in detail:

  1. (A)

    The only respect in which case X differs from case Y concerns the type of co-operation which S receives in his endeavor.

  2. (B)

    This respect provides no reason to ascribe a lesser degree of moral responsibility to S in case X than in case Y.

  3. (C)

    If (A) and (B), then S is just as morally responsible for the outcome in case X as in case Y.

  4. (D)

    In case Y, S is fully morally responsible for the outcome.

So,

  1. (E)

    In case X, S is fully morally responsible for the outcome.

Therefore,

  1. (F)

    In case X, all participants in the action are fully morally responsible for the outcome (Zimmerman 1985a, 117).

I think that Zimmerman’s main argument here is essentially right, although it seems to presuppose that degrees of moral responsibility do not depend upon degrees of causal contribution. This is especially evident in connection with premise (D). It is one thing to claim that someone acts without excuse, so that his or her moral responsibility is undiminished because of co-operating factors; it is another thing to claim that someone is fully morally responsible for something. Full moral responsibility would be responsibility to the highest degree possible, and degree of causal contribution does indeed seem to be relevant to determining this.Footnote 15 Let me explain.

Consider Zimmerman’s agent S, the teenager in case Y who pushed the boulder down the slope and wrecked the car all by himself. Case Y must differ from case X in some respect with regard to the initial conditions, since in case X, the contribution of each teenager is causally necessary for moving the boulder, whereas in case Y, S acts alone to accomplish (roughly) the same thing. Now compare case Y to a third case, Z, which involves just two persons, S and P. Suppose that S casually suggests to P the possibility that P could push the boulder down the slope all by herself, without any (other) help from S; imagine that S then walks away, but thanks to S’s suggestion, P freely decides to do this and does so, where this possibility would not have occurred to P without S’s prompting.

Shouldn’t we say that S’s moral responsibility for the damage to the car in case Z is less than S’s moral responsibility for the damage to the car in case Y? After all, if we hold all of the other factors constant, S’s causal contribution to the wrecking of the car in case Z is not causally sufficient (in the circumstances) for the wrecking of the car, since it must operate “through” P’s free decision to push the boulder down the slope all by herself. (If P’s decision is free, then it is not determined by the prior events, including S’s attempts to persuade.Footnote 16) By contrast, if we hold all of the other factors constant, S’s causal contribution to the wrecking of the car in case Y is causally sufficient (in the circumstances) for the wrecking of the car. Doesn’t this difference clearly indicate different degrees of causal contribution in the two cases, and doesn’t this difference indicate a difference in degrees of moral responsibility in the two cases?

I think so. But Zimmerman offers an argument against this approach. He mentions a variant on his original case X which involves S twisting P’s arm so that P will help S to push the boulder against P’s will, and says this about such a case:

In a case such as that just given it is common and tempting to talk of the differing “extents” to which S and P contributed to the outcome; but I think that such talk should be avoided. Presumably more blame is to be ascribed to S than to P—he is more to blame for the outcome than P is, he is also to blame for twisting P’s arm, and so on—but, given that the action of each is causally necessary and of neither is causally sufficient for the outcome, it seems misleading to talk of S contributing to a greater extent than P to this outcome. In general, it seems to me best to say the following. There is a sense to be attached to the claim that different individuals have more or less “important” roles in the production of an outcome, but such a claim is, first, a normative one and, second, not to be confused with the non-normative issue of contribution to an outcome (a factor which admits of no degrees). (Zimmerman 1985a, 117)

I think that Zimmerman is mistaken here: just because various factors are in themselves neither causally necessary nor causally sufficient for a given outcome, it does not follow that there can be no differences between them in terms of their respective causal contributions. Case Z, involving causal contribution that is non-necessitating, seems to illustrate this clearly; causal contribution is a matter of degree.

Here is another way to illustrate this same point, this time by reference to another hypothetical case from Zimmerman. This case involves group action which is sequential instead of simultaneous:

Imagine a dozen people, with murder on their minds, each delivering one stab to the body of some victim. Let us suppose that each of the stabs is causally necessary for the death to ensue. I submit that, given certain other conditions (full freedom, intent, and so forth), each of the assailants is fully morally responsible for the death. (Zimmerman 1985a, 117)

Zimmerman’s argument for this last claim is essentially similar to the one mentioned earlier in connection with case X: each of the stabs is causally necessary but not causally sufficient, so each of the assailants is morally responsible to the same degree for the outcome. Furthermore, we could imagine a case in which only one of the assailants administered just one stab and killed the victim, and there is no reason to regard that one person’s moral responsibility in the modified case as different from his moral responsibility in the original case involving the twelve people.

But Zimmerman’s case of the dozen stabbers can be modified easily to illustrate different degrees of causal contribution. Suppose that instead of people stabbing, we have a million people, each laying a single straw on the proverbial camel’s back, except for the last person, who lays a hundred straws on the camel’s back (all at once, let’s say).Footnote 17 As before, let’s follow Zimmerman in assuming that each of the million straws is causally necessary for the outcome. Isn’t it obvious that the person who lays a hundred straws at once contributes causally to the breaking of the camel’s back to a greater extent than any of the other people do? This gives us good reason to think that Zimmerman is mistaken here, that causal contribution does come in degrees, and that degrees of causal contribution help to determine degrees of moral responsibility.

However, Zimmerman offers one final argument in this connection that is worth considering. This argument occurs in the context of the evaluation of group action which is oversupplied:

If the argument concerning the possibility of the proper ascription of full moral responsibility to each of the participants in a standard simultaneous group action is successful, then it is easy to argue for this possibility when it is oversupplied rather than standard action that is at issue. Suppose that fifteen teenagers had pushed the boulder instead of ten. This surely would not have diminished the responsibility of any of the original ten. (What an easy “out” that would be! Just invite a few more friends to participate.) (Zimmerman 1985a, 119)

My claim about the relevance of causal contribution to moral responsibility might seem to imply that Zimmerman’s case of oversupplied group action should be diagnosed as involving diminished moral responsibility for the participants. But this apparent implication is only apparent; I agree with Zimmerman’s claim that adding more agents is insufficient, all by itself, to diminish moral responsibility. As Zimmerman says, in another context,

To say that someone is fully responsible is not to say that he is solely responsible; responsibility is not to be cut up, like a pie, so that the more people that join in a wrongdoing, the less responsibility to be allocated to each. (Zimmerman 1985b, 355)

But it is easy to imagine a case which is similar to Zimmerman’s case involving the ten teenagers pushing the boulder in which it does make a difference if more agents are added. For example, suppose that fifteen teenagers are involved instead of ten, and imagine that the causal contribution of each teenager is reduced accordingly (so that the case is not oversupplied, but rather standard, like the original case X). Then it seems reasonable to say that the moral responsibility of a given participant S would be less in this case than it would be in the original case X, all other things being equal. The difference might be slight, of course, and perhaps not important enough to make a difference practically in terms of our response to each individual, but there would be a difference.

Hence I conclude that Zimmerman is mistaken about degrees of causal contribution and that different degrees of causal contribution explain different degrees of moral responsibility, at least in some cases. But notice that along the way, Zimmerman has shown that just because one agent is fully morally responsible for a given event, it does not follow that no other person can be morally responsible for that same event—in other words, the Augustinian premise 12 is false.Footnote 18 How should traditional theists who wish to pursue something like an Augustinian approach to answering the problem of evil respond to this?

It seems to me that they should accept the claim that God is partly morally responsible for evil in the world, but then argue that God’s responsibility does not imply that God is worthy of blame for such evil. This could be done by explaining the reasons that actually justify God’s permission of evil (in the case of theodicy), or explaining the reasons that could justify God’s permission of evil (in the case of defense), or simply explaining why we should not expect to know such reasons if they existed (in the case of the so-called skeptical theism). If these strategies are successful, then either God would be worthy of praise for God’s contributions to such things, or at least God would be neither worthy of praise nor worthy of blame (although satisfying the other requirements for moral responsibility, in the sense mentioned at the beginning of this chapter). Whether or not such strategies can be successful, in terms of explaining how God could be responsible but not blameworthy for evil, falls beyond the scope of this chapter.Footnote 19

3 Conclusion

We should conclude that the ontological randomness involved in creaturely libertarian freedom (should actual creatures possess it, of course) does not by itself imply that God is not morally responsible to any degree for the free actions of creatures, whether good or evil, assuming (as traditional theists do) that God makes some causal contribution to the free actions of creatures. But what about random events that do not involve the free actions of any creatures, such as the random decay of radioactive isotopes?

In cases such as these, it seems important to note that the randomness in question is randomness over a limited range of possible outcomes. In the famous example of Schrödinger’s cat, for instance, there are only two possible states of the radioactive substance in the box with the cat: either it has decayed, or it has not. If it has decayed, then the Geiger counter detects the decay and triggers the hammer to release the poison, which kills the cat. If it has not decayed, then the Geiger counter does not detect the decay and does not trigger the hammer to release the poison, so the cat remains alive. Whether or not the cat is dead, then, involves what I have called ontological randomness. But this arrangement does not involve the possibility of the cat becoming a full-grown horse, a nuclear weapon, or an atom of hydrogen; these last three outcomes are inconsistent with the initial arrangement.

So if God is morally responsible for the fact that a random process is in place that will result in either X or Y, and God knows this, then it seems clear that God is morally responsible to some degree for X if it occurs and morally responsible to some degree for Y if it occurs. Assuming (as I have) that God’s degree of causal contribution to the outcome of a random process is not sufficient to guarantee any particular outcome, we might think that God’s causal contribution in such cases is less than it is in cases in which God’s causal contribution is sufficient to guarantee a particular outcome. But as the discussion of degrees of causal contribution shows, causal contribution and hence moral responsibility come in degrees, so we cannot conclude that those cases that involve God’s causal contribution to random processes are cases in which God’s causal contribution is not necessary or important. Hence traditional theists need not reject Divine Moral Responsibility because of the existence of what I have called ontologically random events in the world.Footnote 20